In 1992 Francis
Fukuyama wrote his influential book The
End of History and the Last Man. The book achieved worldwide interest, at
least in the Anglophone world, so much so that, when I was admitted into law
school in 1995 the claims of the book were still being actively discussed and
its arguments touted in debates within and outside the classroom. Simply put, The End of History claimed that liberal
democracy was the final form of human political evolution. Fukuyama was able to
make this claim for liberal democracy because of the momentous events of those
times, not least of which was the collapse of the Soviet Union. History,
Fukuyama wrote, appeared to culminate in liberty: elected governments,
individual rights, an economic system in which capital and labour circulated
with relatively modest state oversight. He further argued that it would not
mean that every polity would turn into a liberal democracy; rather the
propriety of the liberal state would be so apparent that other political forms
would end their ideological pretensions of representing different and higher
forms of human society even as they continued to exist.
Predictably
Fukuyama’s work was received with howls of protest. There was the usual, and in
my opinion valid, argument: Fukuyama was speaking from a peculiar location that
arrogates to itself a central location in international history and presumes
that what is good for America, is good for the world, and that the view from
the North Atlantic world reveals a clear vision of the world. An outlook of the
world from other vantage points indicates that liberal democracy is not
necessarily seen as a culmination of political institutions. Indeed, while the
centrality of democracy itself is not being challenged, one is witness to
increasing critiques of liberal democracy. Critics point out that there are
substantial problems with Liberalism, and the system is just not
philosophically capable of responding to the diversity of human experiences
without doing serious violence to some groups. Indeed, some would see as the
rise of Islamism as one of the many political ideologies that are countering
the hegemony of liberalism in the world.
Fukuyama’s
argument is important to a Goan audience because it appears that some political
actors in Goa, and representatives of the Indian state in Goa have a similar
position with regard to the end of history in Goa. Take, for example, the responses
to the argument for recognising the legal history that results in persons
resident in the former Estado da Índia (Goans, for the sake of brevity) having
rights of citizenship in Portugal. In this situation, where the Indian state
seems unable to comprehend the situation, and the rights of these Indians are being
held in abeyance, I had argued that it makes sense for concerned Goans to
include the recognition of the right to hold dual citizenship in the charter of
demands in favour of Special Status for Goa. I had argued that such a demand
would do more to protect Goan interests than the exclusive focus on ownership
of land. A focus on restricting land ownership to Goans alone would secure the
interests of landowners more than the rest of the Goan population.
One response to this argument, typical of many Indian apologists, was that of the Commissioner of
NRI Affairs, U. D. Kamat who argued that “[a]s regards ‘Special Status’, it
needs to be appreciated that our political leadership in Goa lost a golden
opportunity to highlight this particular issue before the then Prime Minister,
late Rajiv Gandhi, while canvassing for statehood which was granted in 1987.
Now, with the passage of time and with so many less-developed states pleading
for special status, the central government will not be in a position to
consider our demand as Goa is perceived to be better developed as compared to a
majority of the states of India.”
In other words,
with regards to the question of Special Status, history came to an end in 1987.
No matter how circumstances change, citizens in Goa will be unable to
articulate a new arrangement of power between themselves and the Indian state.
It should be pointed out that Special Status is not the only Goan claim that is
being given short shrift by representatives of the Indian state. Since we are
on the issue of the rights of Goans to hold a dual citizenship, it should be
pointed out that there are some who would argue that the moment for stressing
this right was in 1961, when Goa was integrated into India, or 1974, when
Portugal recognised India’s sovereignty over the territories of the former
Estado da Índia. For these apologists for the Indian state Goan history ended
on these dates and we are now stuck within a political arrangement that will
endure until the end of time.
If Fukuyama’s
arguments smacked of an American arrogance, then the proposition of those who
believe in the end of Goan history is an unspeakable horror. Some defenders of
Fukuyama point out that his formulation of the end of history distinguishes
between events and history. Fukuyama’s argument is not that events will cease,
but that these events will be resolved within the existing liberal-democratic
framework. The liberal state will continue to secure the rights of citizens
within the framework of a democratic regime. The representatives of the Indian
state in Goa, on the other hand, would have it that regardless of the
occurrence of events, there can be no resolution, because the form of Indian
democracy has been fixed and cannot be changed.
There is an extremely popular perspective of history as the continuous expansion of the rights of individuals. In Fukuyama's terms, history is the movement towards liberty. From this perspective, states evolves as they move to secure newer dimensions of rights within changing contexts. If there are demands that Goans be allowed to exercise their rights of citizenship in both Portugal and India, and that Goa be granted a Special Status within the Union of India it is because the passage of time has revealed new ways in which the rights of Goans need to be secured. To claim that it is too late to assert these rights is to make an anti-democratic argument, and in fact suggest that the Indian state is not dynamic enough to accommodate these changes. This would not be an argument in favour of India's continued relevance in the contemporary period and might relegate India itself to the dustbin of history.
(A version of this post was first published in the O Heraldo on 25 Dec 2015)